Read It Is Dangerous to Be Right When the Government Is Wrong Online

Authors: Andrew P. Napolitano

Tags: #ebook, #book

It Is Dangerous to Be Right When the Government Is Wrong (32 page)

BOOK: It Is Dangerous to Be Right When the Government Is Wrong
13.78Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

183

Why does this requirement of necessity and expediency exist? Because the only reason government exists is to secure our liberty, and thus when it criminalizes drinking beer and eating pretzels, not only is it infringing upon the natural right to drink and to eat, it is acting outside the scope of its entire purpose. Thus, the first requirement that government must abide by in the process of drafting and enacting a law is that it is necessary to protect the freedom of persons within the jurisdiction of that government.

The Presumption of Liberty

How then is this procedural requirement of public necessity and expediency enforced? The answer is by means of judicial review, which allows courts to invalidate unconstitutional laws. When learned judges have adequately scrutinized our officials' commands and determined that they stem from the Constitution and do not infringe upon our natural rights, only then are those laws legitimate, giving rise to a moral obligation to obey them. The same moral imperative that lets me do as I please in my own house prevents me from doing as I please in my neighbor's house. That imperative is freedom: The unfettered ability to make personal choices.

By contrast, without judicial review, we would have to trust the legislature and the executive to abide by the Constitution's protections, which for reasons already discussed, is entirely inadequate. For all of their consistent and plentiful historical abuses of the Constitution, we should have no reason to believe that Congress and the President will remain within their constitutionally permitted bounds. It is for this reason that our Founders intended that “the Judges, as expositors of the Laws would have an opportunity of defending [our] constitutional rights.”
1

Sadly, judicial scrutiny of legislative and executive commands has been woefully inadequate, allowing our natural rights to be circumvented time and again. Consider the case of
United States v. Carolene Products
(1938). In 1923, Congress enacted the Filled Milk Act, which banned the interstate sale of skim milk reconstituted with coconut oil. Filled milk became popular during the era as an inexpensive alternative to comparable dairy products; the dairy industry lobbied Congress to eliminate this new source of competition. Although the purpose of the statute was purely to shield the government's friends in the dairy industry, it was not so cleverly passed under the guise of a public health and consumer fraud law: Congress claimed that filled milk was unhealthy, and that it was manufactured to look like real milk, thus confusing consumers. The difficulty was that there was no evidence whatsoever that it was injurious to public health, and the claim that consumers would be “tricked” into buying it was as ridiculous as it sounds; and Congress had no authority to regulate for health or safety. Those bases for law were retained by the Tenth Amendment for the states.

184

In the
Carolene Products
case, the Supreme Court, ever the “impenetrable bulwark against every assumption of power in the legislative or executive,”
2
addressed the constitutionality of the Filled Milk Act. Although it clearly transgressed fundamental economic liberties, interfered with the natural workings of the market, and deprived consumers of the natural right to choose a cheap and perfectly healthy food product, the Court upheld the statute, notwithstanding its constitutionally illegitimate purpose. The Court's reasoning was that the statute should be
presumed
constitutional, and thus the burden was on the defendant company to prove that Congress could have no constitutional authority and no lawful basis for regulating the sale of the product; a nearly impossible showing. By requiring a presumption of constitutionality instead of a presumption of liberty, the Court permitted Congress to transgress economic liberties for almost any reason it wished.

185

The presumption that legislation was constitutional unless proven otherwise first arose during the New Deal era, and its significance in facilitating the growth of the welfare state cannot be overstated. Prior to the presumption of constitutionality, legislatures were required to prove that legislation was necessary (and hence an acceptable regulation of one's liberties) with empirical information; the very information that the legislature would presumably have used in formulating its policy. Thus, if upon surveying the relevant facts, the legislature found there was a dire need for the regulation, the state would of necessity present to a judge its moral and constitutional bases for enacting the legislation, and if the neutral judge agreed, the legislation could be upheld. Only then could laws be legitimate; we could assume that after judges closely scrutinize legislative commands for their constitutional basis and fidelity, those commands really were necessary to safeguard our liberties, and therefore just.

The Court in
Carolene Products
summed up the shift to a presumption of constitutionality as follows:

The existence of facts supporting the legislative judgment is to be presumed, for regulatory legislation affecting ordinary commercial transactions is not to be pronounced unconstitutional unless in the light of the facts made known or generally assumed it is of such a character as to preclude the assumption that it rests upon some rational basis within the knowledge and experience of the legislators.

This presumption of constitutionality, however, was not to be limited to economic liberties, but was to be the norm; the burden would only shift in very limited circumstances—circumstances so limited that they did not warrant reference in the main body of the opinion, but merely a footnote. Those limited circumstances would be where the statute violates an express provision of the Constitution, where it infringes upon the workings of the political process, or targets discrete and insular minorities.

Later cases, such as
Griswold v. Connecticut
(1965), established that certain judicially hand-picked “unenumerated” rights would also be entitled to similar treatment. In that case, Justice Goldberg, in his concurrence, noted that there was a “right of marital privacy,” which extended far enough to protect the decision to take contraceptives, and sufficient to force the government to prove its case criminalizing the use of contraceptives.

186

Related to this burden of proof—the legal obligation of producing evidence and making a persuasive argument to a court—was what the individual actually needed to prove to demonstrate that legislation was unconstitutional. In the
Carolene Products
case, the Court stated that the individual challenging the law must demonstrate that there could be
no rational basis
for the statute; a legal element which has proven itself to be nearly impossible to satisfy. As for those limited, judicially determined circumstances where the burden shifts to the government, cases established that the state must have a compelling interest, and the means used to actuate that interest must be narrowly tailored so as to do the least amount of damage to fundamental liberties. This legal doctrine has resulted in a jumbled mess where racial affirmative action is scrutinized more closely than gender discrimination, and there is a fundamental right to take contraceptives, but not to establish paternity over a biological child. In essence, it is a system where recognized rights rest on tenuous legal grounds, and liberties on which our Constitution bases its legitimacy are only marginally protected.

The presumption of constitutionality is the central flaw of this entire system. It will be the individual who will have the burden of presenting that evidence. However, one must ask, Why should the individual have to present empirical data, rather than the governmental officials who gathered and relied upon that data in crafting policy? It is simply inefficient to place this burden on the individual; doing so is more burdensome. Might the government have advanced and secured the presumption of constitutionality—and the concomitant burden of disproving it upon the persons whose liberties the government has violated—in order to assure its maintenance and possession of its coercive powers? In a word:
Yes
. Thus, because the individual has inadequate access to information, it increases the chance that he will lose even where that evidence clearly and convincingly shows that the statute was unconstitutional.

As a simple matter of fundamental fairness, shouldn't it be the one who encroaches upon liberty who has to show why he is justified in doing so? Certainly, this principle would apply to individuals; why not government as well? If someone on the street walks up to you and randomly punches you in the face, is it fair to assume that he was acting in self-defense, and you should carry the burden of proving otherwise? Would your answer change if the puncher was a police officer instead of a private citizen? Recall that all individuals are subject to Natural Law, as are all governments, which are merely human inventions. To suggest that governments should somehow be treated differently from individuals in how Natural Law applies to them is to violate the truths that Natural Law transcends the temporal, and that the order of things governs those things themselves.

187

Moreover, shouldn't the burden of proving the justification of an action which is adverse to another always fall on whoever is trying to take that action? Why is it that you said in our hypothetical above that the puncher should have the burden of showing he was acting in self-defense? Because the person taking an action which is adverse to freedom always has the moral duty to justify his actions. It is the same moral imperative not to restrict your neighbor's unfettered ability to make personal choices, like the choice to buy filled milk. To say otherwise is to assume that actions which are adverse to freedom are acceptable, and thus you are superior to your neighbor. Similarly, every government command restricts liberty.
Government is, in essence, the negation of liberty
. The burden of showing why government is justified cannot morally shift to the individual, the object of that restriction of liberty. To say otherwise is to say that the individual is inferior to the government, a myth which we have thoroughly rejected by now.

Another problem with the presumption of constitutionality arises where the evidence of unconstitutionality is of a “controversial and indeterminate” nature. In these cases the presumption will invariably win the day for the government. Thus, as a practical matter, the government is no longer bound by the Constitution unless evidence is clear and convincing. This has allowed government to circumvent constitutional constraints and encroach upon our liberties. Its justification? “You couldn't prove otherwise.” Or, in other words, the government can violate your liberty if you cannot provide a legally sufficient answer to the question “Why not!?”

Such has been the case with nearly any restriction of economic liberties. In
Williamson v. Lee Optical
(1955), the Court upheld an Oklahoma statute which made it criminal for an optician to repair lenses without the patient first obtaining a new prescription every time. Did it matter that the statute had no ostensibly legitimate purpose, and was not even rationally related to any purpose at all (except to reward the lobbying efforts of Oklahoman optometrists)? Writing for the Court, Justice Douglas stated that “the law need not be in every respect logically consistent with its aims to be constitutional.” In another, less subtle word: NO.

188

What is even more infuriating is the belittling view of our rights adopted by the Court, which necessarily accompanied this deference to the legislature (recall that government is the negation of liberty). What of our economic liberties? Those were viewed by the Court as vestiges of an outdated economic “school of thought” (laissez-faire). And in
Plessy v. Ferguson
(1896), good law until
Brown v. Board of Education
(1954), the Court chided that if African Americans felt humiliated by racial segregation, “it is not by reason of anything found in the act, but solely because the colored race chooses to put that construction upon it.” In sum, if we felt morally outraged by these statutes, it was purely the product of our own heterodox views, not the transgression of our constitutionally protected natural rights.

But, one may ask, doesn't it cut the other way? That is, won't there be a number of cases where the government was genuinely authorized by the Constitution to take some action, but it just couldn't prove why or how it was constitutional with evidence? The answer is NO, because the only time government is supposed to act is when it is morally and constitutionally justified in doing so, that is, when it has evidence demonstrating not only a rational basis, but a necessity. Anything less would permit arbitrary—or even worse, invidious—government restrictions of liberty. Thus, the presumption of constitutionality can serve no legitimate purpose other than to increase the scope of the government's authority beyond the Constitution.

It should be clear at this point that the presumption of constitutionality disparages our Constitution in principle, and our unenumerated natural rights in practice. But as a practical matter, how then are we to protect all of our unenumerated liberties, as the Constitution requires, without actually listing them? The answer is, of course,
a presumption of liberty
.

189

What Is a “Law,” After All?

In
Papachristou v. City of Jacksonville
(1972), the Supreme Court considered the constitutionality of the following ordinance, which provided for the arrest and conviction of

rogues and vagabonds, or dissolute persons who go about begging, common gamblers, persons who use juggling or unlawful games or plays, common drunkards, common night walkers, thieves, pilferers or pickpockets, traders in stolen property, lewd, wanton and lascivious persons, keepers of gambling places, common railers and brawlers, persons
wandering or strolling around from place to place without any lawful purpose or object
, habitual loafers, disorderly persons, persons neglecting all lawful business and habitually spending their time by frequenting houses of ill fame, gaming houses, or places where alcoholic beverages are sold or served, [and] persons able to work but habitually living upon the earnings of their wives or minor children. (emphasis added)

BOOK: It Is Dangerous to Be Right When the Government Is Wrong
13.78Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

Luna Tick: A Sunshine Novel by Merriam, Angie
Dragons Don't Cry by Suzie Ivy
Reddened Wasteland by Kyle Perkins
Count Geiger's Blues by Michael Bishop
Dahmer Flu by Cox, Christopher
The Woman from Bratislava by Leif Davidsen